model category, model -category
Definitions
Morphisms
Universal constructions
Refinements
Producing new model structures
Presentation of -categories
Model structures
for -groupoids
on chain complexes/model structure on cosimplicial abelian groups
related by the Dold-Kan correspondence
for equivariant -groupoids
for rational -groupoids
for rational equivariant -groupoids
for -groupoids
for -groups
for -algebras
general -algebras
specific -algebras
for stable/spectrum objects
for -categories
for stable -categories
for -operads
for -categories
for -sheaves / -stacks
homotopy theory, (∞,1)-category theory, homotopy type theory
flavors: stable, equivariant, rational, p-adic, proper, geometric, cohesive, directed…
models: topological, simplicial, localic, …
see also algebraic topology
Introductions
Definitions
Paths and cylinders
Homotopy groups
Basic facts
Theorems
A model category structure on some category is a means to guarantee the local smallness and to improve the tractability of the homotopy category of the underlying category with weak equivalences . In particular, if a category with weak equivalences admits a model category structure, then its homotopy category (in the sense of localization at the class of weak equivalences) is equivalent to the category of bifibrant objects whose morphisms are the actual homotopy classes of morphisms between them (left homotopy or right homotopy equivalence classes in the sense of homotopy in a model category) .
Let be a model category. Write for the category whose
objects are the bifibrant objects of ;
morphisms are the homotopy classes of morphisms of , hence the equivalence classes of morphism under left homotopy.
This is, up to equivalence of categories, the homotopy category of the model category .
We spell out that def. indeed satisfies the universal property that defines the homotopy category of a category with weak equivalences.
(Whitehead theorem in model categories)
Let be a model category. A weak equivalence between bifibrant objects is a homotopy equivalence.
(e.g. Goerss-Jardine 99, part I, theorem 1.10)
By the factorization axioms in , every weak equivalence factors through an object as an acyclic cofibration followed by an acyclic fibration. In particular it follows that with and both bifibrant, so is , and hence it is sufficient to prove that acyclic (co-)fibrations between such objects are homotopy equivalences.
So let be an acyclic fibration between fibrant-cofibrant objects, the case of acyclic cofibrations is formally dual. Then in fact it has a genuine right inverse given by a lift in the diagram
To see that is also a left inverse up to left homotopy, let be any cylinder object on , hence a factorization of the codiagonal on as a cofibration followed by a an acyclic fibration
and consider the square
which commutes due to being a genuine right inverse of . By construction, this commuting square now admits a lift , and that constitutes a left homotopy .
Given a model category , consider a choice for each object of
a factorization of the initial morphism, such that when is already cofibrant then ;
a factorization of the terminal morphism, such that when is already fibrant then .
Write then
for the functor to the homotopy category, def. , which sends an object to the object and sends a morphism to the homotopy class of the result of first lifting in
and then lifting (here: extending) in
First of all, the object is indeed both fibrant and cofibrant (as well as related by a zig-zag of weak equivalences to ):
Now to see that the image on morphisms is well defined. First observe that any two choices of the first lift in the definition are left homotopic to each other, exhibited by lifting in
Hence also the composites are left homotopic to each other, and since their domain is cofibrant, they are also right homotopic (via this lemma) by a right homotopy . This implies finally, by lifting in
that also and are right homotopic, hence that indeed represents a well-defined homotopy class.
Finally to see that the assignment is indeed functorial, observe that the commutativity of the lifting diagrams for and imply that also the following diagram commutes
Now from the pasting composite
one sees that is a lift of and hence the same argument as above gives that it is homotopic to the chosen .
For a category with weak equivalences, its homotopy category (or: localization at the weak equivalences) is, if it exists, a category equipped with a functor
which sends weak equivalences to isomorphisms, and which is universal with this property:
for any functor out of into any category, such that takes weak equivalences to isomorphisms, it factors through up to a natural isomorphism
and this factorization is unique up to unique isomorphism, in that for and two such factorizations, then there is a unique natural isomorphism making the evident diagram of natural isomorphisms commute.
For a model category, the functor in def. (for any choice of and ) exhibits as indeed being the homotopy category of the underlying category with weak equivalences, in the sense of def. .
First, to see that that indeed takes weak equivalences to isomorphisms: By two-out-of-three applied to the commuting diagrams shown in the proof of lemma the morphism is a weak equivalence if is:
With this the “Whitehead theorem for model categories”, lemma , implies that represents an isomorphism in .
Now let be any functor that sends weak equivalences to isomorphisms. We need to show that it factors as
uniquely up to unique natural isomorphism. Now by construction of and in def. , is the identity on the full subcategory of fibrant-cofibrant objects. It follows that if exists at all, it must satisfy for all with and both fibrant and cofibrant that
But by def. that already fixes on all of , up to unique natural isomorphism. Hence it only remains to check that with this definition of there exists any natural isomorphism filling the diagram above.
To that end, apply to the above commuting diagram to obtain
Here now all horizontal morphisms are isomorphisms, by assumption on . It follows that defining makes the required natural isomorphism:
Due to theorem we may suppress the choices of cofibrant and fibrant replacement in def. and just speak of the localization functor
up to natural isomorphism.
While the construction of the homotopy category in def. combines the restriction to good (fibrant/cofibrant) objects with the passage to homotopy classes of morphisms, it is often useful to consider intermediate stages:
Given a model category , write
for the system of full subcategory inclusions on the cofibrant objects (), the fibrant objects () and the objects which are both fibrant and cofibrant (), all regarded a categories with weak equivalences, via the weak equivalences inherited from .
Of course the subcategories in def. inherit more structure than just that of categories with weak equivalences from . and each inherit “half” of the factorization axioms. One says that has the structure of a “fibration category” called a “category of fibrant objects”, while has the structure of a “cofibration category”.
The proof of theorem immediately implies the following:
For a model category, the restriction of the localization functor from def. (using remark ) to any of the sub-categories with weak equivalences of def.
exhibits equivalently as the homotopy category also of these subcategories. In particular there are equivalences of categories
In fact, for computing hom-sets in the homotopy category, it is sufficient that the domain is cofibrant and the codomain is fibrant:
For with cofibrant and fibrant, and for fibrant/cofibrant replacement functors as in def. , the morphism
(on homotopy classes of morphisms, well defined by prop. ) is a natural bijection.
We may factor the morphism in question as the composite
This shows that it is sufficient to see that for cofibrant and fibrant, then
is an isomorphism, and dually that
is an isomorphism. We discuss this for the former; the second is formally dual:
First, that is surjective is the lifting property in
which says that any morphism comes from a morphism under postcomposition with .
Second, that is injective is the lifting property in
which says that if two morphisms become homotopic after postcomposition with , then they were already homotopic before.
For and two categories with weak equivalences, then a functor is called homotopical functor if it sends weak equivalences to weak equivalences.
Given a homotopical functor (def. ) between categories with weak equivalences whose homotopy categories and exist (def. ), then its derived functor is the functor between these homotopy categories which is induced uniquely, up to unique isomorphism, by their universal property (def. ):
While many functors of interest between model categories are not homotopical in the sense of def. , many become homotopical after restriction to the full subcategories of fibrant object or of cofibrant objects, def. . By corollary this is just as good for the purpose of homotopy theory.
Therefore one considers the following generalization of def. :
Consider a functor out of a model category into a category with weak equivalences .
If the restriction of to the full subcategory of fibrant object becomes a homotopical functor (def. ), then the derived functor of that restriction, according to def. , is called the right derived functor of and denoted by :
Here the commuting square on the left is from corollary , the square on the right is that of def. .
If the restriction of to the full subcategory of cofibrant object becomes a homotopical functor (def. ), then the derived functor of that restriction, according to def. , is called the left derived functor of and denoted by :
Here the commuting square on the left is from corollary , the square on the right is that of def. .
The key fact that makes def. practically useful is the following
Let be a model category with full subcategories of fibrant objects and of cofibrant objects respectively (def. ). Let be a category with weak equivalences.
A functor
is a homotopical functor, def. , already if it sends acylic fibrations to weak equivalences.
A functor
is a homotopical functor, def. , already if it sends acylic cofibrations to weak equivalences.
Let be model categories and consider a functor. Then:
If preserves cofibrant objects and acyclic cofibrations between these, then its left derived functor (def. ) exists, fitting into a diagram
If preserves fibrant objects and acyclic fibrants between these, then its right derived functor (def. ) exists, fitting into a diagram
In practice it turns out to be useful to arrange for the assumptions in corollary to be satisfied in the following neat way:
Let be model categories. A pair of adjoint functors between them
is called a Quillen adjunction (and , are called left/right Quillen functors, respectively) if the following equivalent conditions are satisfied
preserves cofibrations and preserves fibrations;
preserves acyclic cofibrations and preserves acyclic fibrations;
preserves cofibrations and acylic cofibrations;
preserves fibrations and acyclic fibrations.
Observe that
(i) A left adjoint between model categories preserves acyclic cofibrations precisely if its right adjoint preserves fibrations.
(ii) A left adjoint between model categories preserves cofibrations precisely if its right adjoint preserves acyclic fibrations.
We discuss statement (i), statement (ii) is formally dual. So let be an acyclic cofibration in and a fibration in . Then for every commuting diagram as on the left of the following, its -adjunct is a commuting diagram as on the right here:
If preserves acyclic cofibrations, then the diagram on the right has a lift, and so the -adjunct of that lift is a lift of the left diagram. This shows that has the right lifting property against all acylic cofibrations and hence is a fibration. Conversely, if preserves fibrations, the same argument run from right to left gives that preserves acyclic fibrations.
Now by repeatedly applying (i) and (ii), all four conditions in question are seen to be equivalent.
For two model categories, a Quillen adjunction (def.)
is called a Quillen equivalence if the following equivalent conditions hold.
The right derived functor of (via prop. , corollary ) is an equivalence of categories
The left derived functor of (via prop. , corollary ) is an equivalence of categories
For every cofibrant object and every fibrant object , a morphism is a weak equivalence precisely if its adjunct morphism is
For every cofibrant object , the derived adjunction unit, hence the composite
(of the adjunction unit with any fibrant replacement) is a weak equivalence.
For every fibrant object the derived adjunction counit, hence the composite
(of the adjunction counit with any cofibrant replacement) is a weak equivalence.
For a Quillen adjunction between model categories, also the corresponding left and right derived functors form a pair of adjoint functors
between the corresponding homotopy categories.
Moreover, the adjunction unit and adjunction counit of this derived adjunction are the images of the derived adjunction unit and derived adjunction counit of the original Quillen adjunction.
This construction extends to a double pseudofunctor
on the double category of model categories (this Prop.).
The original account:
Review:
William Dwyer, J. Spalinski, Homotopy theories and model categories (pdf) in Ioan Mackenzie James (ed.), Handbook of Algebraic Topology 1995
Paul Goerss, Rick Jardine, section II.1 of Simplicial homotopy theory Birkhäuser 1999, 2009
Introduction to Homotopy Theory, this Section
(where the above material is mostly taken from)
The higher variant of homotopy 2-categories of model categories:
Last revised on June 6, 2024 at 10:20:38. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.